Date:
Mon, 19 Sep 2005 08:11:01 -0400
From:
David Cheifetz
Subject:
Apportionment, Causative Potency, Blameworthiness
Charles,
I
hope I haven't fallen into the trap of failing to keep separate
the issues of the wrongdoers' liability and the extent of that liability
to P from the issues of how to apportion financial responsibility
between the wrongdoers. You are both right and wrong, I think, to
point out that it's a non-sequitur to argue merely from the proposition
that the fiduciary and assistant are jointly liable to P, as joint
wrongdoers, that as between themselves they necessarily ought to
be equally responsible for the loss. Canadian authority, in fact,
doesn't require that conclusion. The nature of the duty breached
by each of the wrongdoers is relevant to the apportionment. I suspect
that if I searched, I'd find a case where the fact that T1 was the
fiduciary and T2 the assistant resulted in T1 having a greater share.
On the other hand, I think it just as likely we'd find sufficient
involvement on the part of T2, even if not a fiduciary, to move
the significance of T2's conduct sufficiently close to the level
of T1's that the apportionments wouldn't be significantly different.
My
point, though, is that on the assumption P1 and P2 are joint wrongdoers,
it seems to me there's a logical inconsistency in that result (the
greater share to T1) if the central basis for apportionment is causative
potency. That inconsistency exists because, as joint wrongdoers,
the conduct of one is the conduct of all, if apply the consequences
of that deeming even in apportionment. To eliminate the inconsistency,
we have to add, in the apportionment context, that the deeming of
the conduct does not carry with it the moral approbation. I see
no principled reason preventing that approach. The issues at the
apportionment stage are sufficiently different that principle doesn't
require that T2 always be deemed to be treated as if T2 had actually
acted as T1 did. It's just that, if one does that, I think logic
requires the realization that the consequence is inconsistent with
the causative potency of all of the acts which the law deems to
be T2's. Put another way, you are apportioning financial responsibility
based only on the causative potency of T2's own acts. Again, there's
nothing wrong with that distinction, particularly given the underpinning
of the contribution remedy in UE. It just needs to be made clear
that that is what is happening.
Anyway,
I rather suspect that in most cases of the sort you are describing,
we would have a finding that the assistant's conduct creates direct
liability on the assistant and that that conduct was causative,
given the current summary of the law required for T2 to be liable
in such circumstances. See the summary in Commercial
Union Life Assurance Co. of Canada v. John Ingle Insurance Group
Inc., 2002 CanLII 45028 (Ont CA) at para 2-4 where the
Ont CA summarizes the current law relating to the "nature of
the breach of trust required to impose liability on a stranger for
knowing assistance". I haven't thought it through but, on first
blush, it seems to me that Canada's retention of the broad approach
to the principles of tort liability that flows from Anns v Merton,
which England has (somewhat ?) resiled from, might be relevant to
explaining our approach.
I've
been lax, the past two plus decades, in keeping up with cases that
might affect how one meshes the traditional consequences of joint
wrongdoing with apportionment legislation insofar as those consequences
affect apportionment as between the wrongdoers . I'm reasonably
certain the issue, put that way, is often considered; at least because
there is a tendency in Canadian courts to say that the apportionment
legislation means its no longer necessary to consider whether the
wrongdoers are joint, so long as there's a finding that their conduct
caused the same damages. (We've generally managed to avoid the damage
/ damages problem, so far.) I assume that one or more of the members
of this list will know, of hand, if there are Canadian cases where
the court has specifically considered how the apportionment is affected
by the fact that T1 was the actual fiduciary and T2 merely the assistant.
CGU doesn't assist, really, because the person who would have been
T2 in your construct (John Ingle) wasn't found liable at all based
on Canadian law and the conduct of the other person who was a stranger
to the trust was sufficiently egregious as to create direct, personal
liability for that conduct.
Regards,
David
-----
Original Message -----
From: Charles Mitchell
To: David Cheifetz
Sent: Monday, September 19, 2005 5:26 AM
Subject: ODG: Re: Apportionment, Causative Potency, Blameworthiness
Dear
David
I'll
certainly go back and read Atiyah's piece: thanks for the reference.
But my snap answer so far as the trustee/dishonest assistant example
is concerned is that this is one of those rare situations contemplated
by Atiyah where
it
can be clearly demonstrated that the assistance of one of the
parties made no difference to the result.
Under
English law at least, the causation rules for dishonest assistance
are unusual because the courts have recognised liability under
this head as a kind of civil secondary liability analogous to
criminal secondary liability - a step which they refused to take
at common law in Credit Lyonnais v ECGD [2000] 1 AC 164.
See most recently Ultraframe (UK) Ltd v Fielding [2005]
EWHC 1638 (Ch) [1506] (Lewison J).
Hence,
to establish liability all that needs to be proved against a dishonest
assistant is that he did something which made the defaulting fiduciary's
breach of duty easier than it would otherwise have been: Brown
v Bennett [1999] 1 BCLC 649 at 659. Hence he may be liable
even if the loss would have occurred anyway.
On
your argument, it follows from the fact that a dishonest assistant
D1 and a defaulting fiduciary D2 are jointly and severally liable
to the principal, that when it comes to apportion between D1 and
D2, the law must deem them to have caused the principal's loss
jointly and thus to the same extent.
But
I believe this to be a non sequitur. As between D1 and the principal,
the law wishes to make D1 liable to the same extent as D2, even
though the causative impact of his actions has been less, because
he is a very bad guy, subjectively dishonest. But it does not
follow from this that as between D1 and D2, the law must apportion
as though the causative impact of their actions was identical.
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index
~ Next
Message
>>>>>
|