Date:
Mon, 24 Jun 2002 15:53:14 -0400
From:
Jason Neyers
Subject:
Fairchild Discussion
Dear
Colleagues,
Vaughan
Black and I started a discussion about Fairchild by personal e-mail and
in the spirit of getting debate going on the ODG we have decided to post
the discussion:
---------------------------
QUESTION:
JN
Vaughan,
what did you think of Fairchild?
RESPONSE:
VB
Well
for what it's worth . . . thought that Fairchild was a pretty good judgment.
It's far preferable to the SCC cases on the material contribution test
in that it (1) defines with some precision the areas in which that test
should be available (though of course leaving things open to develop by
analogy) and (2) makes a pretty fair stab at articulating what the test
means.
There
are also some useful statements disparaging those silly comments judges
make to the effect that "causation is just a matter of comment sense"
-- which always struck me as little more than a judicial refusal to explain
what they were doing.
Now
if they could just stop saying "causation is a matter of policy", which,
since they hardly ever explain quite what they mean by "policy", is an
equally silly statement, then we might start to get somewhere.
vb
Response:
JN
Dear
Vaughan,
Very
interesting. I think that I have the exact opposite conclusion on most
issues except for policy where I agree totally.
I
prefer the SCC approach in that material contribution (or its more refined
cousin NESS) is the test of factual causation that applies across the
law. The "but for" test is the simplification of this that works in most
cases but it is only a simplification, like Newtonian physics is for quantum
mechanics. Hence there does not need to be a test for when to use material
contribution as opposed to "but for" except a rule of thumb: If you get
a negative with "but for", test it with NESS.
I
also think that the judges are right to say that proof of causation (measured
to NESS) in situations of causal uncertainty is a common-sense proposition:
hence if you prove that the defendant's negligence materially contributed
to the risk that X would occur and X did occur, it is open to the trier
of fact to draw the inference that in this state of imperfect medical
knowledge the defendant materially contributed to the injury of the plaintiff.
The
problem with some of the Lords is that they seem to treat statements of
doctors who are basing their premises on scientific measures of knowledge
(i.e. near certainty) as if they controlled the law's separate approach
to the matter (balance of probabilities).
For
those reasons, I prefer Lord Hutton who basically says that what has hitherto
been open to the judge (inference of fact) should now be done routinely
(inference of law).
JN
RESPONSE:
VB
Jason,
Insofar
as statements such as "causation is just commonsense" serve to remind
us that causation in law is different from causation in science (e.g.
Farrell v. Snell) I have not problem with them. But an increasingly common
deployment of so-called commonsense -- one that corresponds with what
Thoreau had in mind when he wrote that common sense always takes the hasty
and superficial view -- is one which seeks to juxtapose commonsense with
philosophy. Thus the famous and oft-cited quotation from Alphacell --
"we're not doing philosophy here; we're doing law" (or something to that
effect, I'm quoting from memory). And while I quite agree that judging
differs from philosophizing, the main use to which the Alphacell quotation
is put seems little more than a refusal to engage in rigorous thought.
It's not unlike responding to the problem that a term like "reasonable
doubt" is difficult to define by simply deciding that the only instruction
to juries in murder cases should be something like "find the accused guilty
if, according to your common sense, you think he deserves to spend the
rest of his life in prison".
I
think that where we differ is that I just don't see MC as a version of
NESS, at least not the way MC is applied by the SCC in Walker. There it's
not just a response to evidentiary uncertainty. Maybe we could clarify
matters with a simple case: do you think Barnett v. Chelsea Hospital was
rightly decided, or do you see it as a case where MC should have been
applied to find liability? I think it was rightly decided, despite the
fact that one could say that the defendant's carelessness materially increased
the risk of the sort of harm that Barnett suffered. (Perhaps you think
that's not so in that Barnett, by the time he got to the hospital, was
already dead man walking, and so could not be subjected to any further
risk of death.)
VB
RESPONSE:
JN
Dear
Vaughan,
Thanks
for your response.
I
do think that Barnett is right but on the lines that he was a dead man
walking. There is no causal uncertainty in that case because it is one
of pre-emptive causation (to use Wright's term (R. Wright, "Causation
in Tort Law")).
I
would save the "commonsense argument" for a true case of causal uncertainty
where I agree with Lord Bridge that if it looks like causation and smells
like causation, then in the absence of other evidence, and on the balance
of probabilities, one may infer that there was causation (i.e. that the
negligence of the defendant materially contributed to the injury suffered
by the plaintiff). Do you have another case to test our differences?
JN
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|