Date:
Thu, 24 Jul 2003 11:28:44 -0400
From:
Jason Neyers
Subject:
New PC decision on Libel Awards
Dear
Colleagues,
Well
what a debate :)!
As
Harold has noted, the nature of the disagreements between us call for
a much longer argument than can be made in an e-mail. I will only say
that it appears that he and I have very different concepts on the proper
role of the judge in a constitutional democracy when deciding private
law cases. I would also question in passing what seem to me to be two
underlying and related hypotheses of his arguments:
1) That the fact that a particular decision has distributional consequences
means that the reasoning which arrived at it is 'political' and therefore
political concerns are relevant to that particular exercise of decision-making.
2) That when a legal question is particularly difficult, i.e. where reasonable
minds applying the law can disagree, the door is then open to import whatever
reasons the judge finds helpful in reaching a conclusion. (For an interesting
take on these two hypothesis, see Steven J. Burton, Judging in Good
Faith (Cambridge, CUP, 1992).
I
would also point out that my quotation of Lord Goff was given not on the
basis that it was authoritative as a matter of stare decisis, but
rather on the basis that I took it to be a well-reasoned response to the
arguments made by Lord Hoffmann (which as Harold notes were endorsed by
the rest of the board).
Though
if the matter came down to duelling authorities, I would hazard a guess
that there would be more support for the proposition that matters of insurance
are irrelevant to liability and damages than for the converse ("As Viscount
Simonds noted in Lister v. Romford Ice & Cold Storage Co., [1957]
1 All E.R. 125 (H.L.) at p. 133: 'As a general proposition it has not,
I think, been questioned for nearly two hundred years that, in determining
the rights inter se of A and B, the fact that one or other of them is
insured is to be disregarded'" per CORY J., speaking for the majority
of the SCC in Dobson (Litigation Guardian of) v. Dobson, (1999)
174 D.L.R. (4th) 1 (SCC)).
Sincerely,
Jason
Harold
Luntz wrote:
Jason's
response to my brief comment calls, I fear, for a lengthy reply - one
much longer than I can give here. It raises three questions:
1.
Did Lord Hoffmann gratuitously bring in to this case issues relating
to damages for non-pecuniary loss in personal injury cases?
2.
Is it relevant to the measure of damages for non-pecuniary loss to consider
who actually pays the damages?
3.
What is meant by "compensation" for non-pecuniary loss?
Let
me try to answer them as briefly as I can. By way of preliminary let
me say that Lord Hoffmann was speaking on behalf of a unanimous PC (the
days when dissenting judgments were not allowed in the PC ceased in
1965, I think it was). Presumably four other judges endorsed his remarks.
1.
This is the easiest to answer. The argument before the PC was that,
in assessing the damages for libel in this case, the Jamaican courts
wrongly refused to consider the level of damages for personal injury.
The PC held that the Jamaican courts were not wrong in so doing. It
was clearly relevant to explain why this was so. One of the reasons
given was that personal injury damages may be influenced by factors
that may not have the same weight in libel cases. So it was relevant
to consider what differences there are between the damages awarded in
the two types of case. One answer given by Lord Hoffmann is that personal
injury judgments are mostly paid by insurers, not the defendants themselves,
and the premiums are not very sensitive to claims. Libel damages, on
the other hand, may be paid by the defendants themselves or, if paid,
by insurers, premiums are likely to be adjusted. This could account
for differences between the types of judgment.
2.
Jason says this is all irrelevant in "a judgment that purports to being
about doing justice as between the joined parties". He invokes some
authority against the use of distributive justice. That authority is
found in a dissenting judgment. Be that as it may, let me also invoke
authority, a much more concise statement: "The law should, so far as
possible, avoid fictions" (Kirby J in 3. Even if one were concerned
with pure corrective justice, what does compensation for non-pecuniary
loss really mean? Years ago, Patrick Atiyah, in a remark recently quoted
with approval by the Panel that reviewed the Law of Negligence in Australia,
said: (1998) 192 CLR 330 at [231]). We all know that most personal injury
damages are not paid by the named defendants. The damages are paid from
insurance premiums or the prices of goods and services for which all
of us pay. Leaving aside non-pecuniary damages, the tort system redistributes
wealth from the poor to the rich because damages are largely earnings-related.
When two people buy a defective product in the supermarket, they pay
the same price, but the higher earner of the two receives larger damages
if unable to work in consequence. I doubt that Lord Hoffmann was particularly
concerned about his own car insurance premium (in any event, he was
- maybe still is - a noted bicycle rider). He was probably more concerned
about the poor motorist who may be unable to afford the premium to run
a car at all if damages are not kept to a level that society can afford
or the sick person who can't be treated in a NHS hospital because resources
have been diverted to paying damages.
There
appears to be simply no way of working out any relationship between
the value of money - what it will buy - and damages awarded for pain
and suffering and disabilities. All such damages awards could be multiplied
or divided by two overnight and they would be just as defensible or
indefensible as they are today.
In
other words, when the Supreme Court of Canada fixed the upper level
of damages for non-pecuniary loss in Canada at $100,000 (since increased
only for inflation), they could just as well have chosen $200,000 or
$50,000 and no one could say they were definitely wrong. The English
Law Commission tried valiantly to arrive at the "appropriate" level
of compensation in their report in 1999, commissioning (non-armchair)
empirical research, including Hazel Genn's "How Much is Enough?" They
recommended that legislation should be avoided, but failed to completely
convince the five experienced judges (not including Lord Hoffmann) in
Heil v Rankin [2001] QB 272 (CA) to increase the level as much
as they wanted it to be. Maybe we would all (or some of us - "armchair
empiricism"?) like to see more damages paid to injured persons, but
if the courts do it, that too is a political judgment, which can't be
avoided. If the level of damages is increased by the judges, we must
recognise it as a form of taxation without representation. We in Australia
are presently seeing a democratic backlash against what is perceived
to be over-generous compensation by judges. Much of it is misguided
and due to false perceptions, but the parliaments are giving effect
to the wishes of those who squeal loudest.
Harold
Luntz.
Jason
Neyers
Assistant Professor of Law
Faculty of Law
University of Western Ontario
N6A 3K7
(519) 661-2111 x. 88435
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|