Date:
Mon, 29 Sep 2003 12:38:20 -0500
From:
Richard Wright
Subject:
Articles on the meaning of negligence and the extent of legal responsibility
(Sorry for any overlap with the tort professors list
at tortprof@chicagokent.kentlaw.edu,
to which I sent this message yesterday. If you are a teacher of
tort law who is not a member of that list but would like to be,
send a "subscribe tortprof your- name" message to listproc@chicagokent.kentlaw.edu.
For good or ill, it is a not very active list.)
Several of my recent articles, which are available
at http://papers.ssrn.com/authorid=146352,
may be of interest to the members of the list, especially those
currently teaching the basic torts course.
The Meaning of Negligence
Three of the articles - "Justice and Reasonable Care
in Negligence Law" ("Justice"), "Negligence in the Courts: Introduction
and Commentary" ("Courts"), and "Hand, Posner, and the Myth of the
'Hand Formula'" ("Myth") - discuss the divergence between the utilitarian-efficiency
conception of negligence or reasonableness that is pervasive in
the secondary literature and the rights-based conception that is
employed by ordinary people and the courts.
The secondary literature generally assumes that negligence
is defined by an aggregate-risk-utility ("Hand formula") test, which
is a transparent implementation of the impartiality and aggregation
principles of utilitarianism and the usual (Kaldor-Hicks) interpretation
of economic efficiency. Although it has sometimes been argued otherwise,
this test is fundamentally inconsistent with the equal freedom norm
that underlies the principles of justice, as all the leading justice
theorists now insist. (See "Justice.") The various editions of the
Restatement of Torts have all supported the aggregate-risk-utility
test. However, unlike the draft Restatement Third's explicit, reductionist,
cost-benefit test, the first and second Restatements emphasize legally
recognized, socially valuable benefits rather than purely private
benefits and employ illustrations that treat the creation of significant
risks to others as reasonable only if they are non-serious, inherent
risks of activities that cannot be further reduced without the loss
of much greater benefits to everyone in society. (See "Justice.")
Recent studies all conclude that the aggregate-risk-utility
test had almost no support in the cases prior to its adoption in
the first Restatement and for several decades thereafter. Richard
Posner's claims to the contrary are composed of speculative and
implausible assumptions, overbroad generalizations, and superficial
descriptions of and quotations from cases that misstate or ignore
facts, language, rationales, and holdings that are inconsistent
with his argument. None of the cases discussed by Posner support
his thesis. Instead, the reasoning and results in these cases employ
varying standards of care, depending on the rights and relationships
among the parties, that are inconsistent with the aggregate-risk-utility
test but consistent with the principles of justice. (See "Myth.")
The aggregate-risk-utility test does not appear in standard jury
instructions. The courts infrequently mention it, rarely attempt
to actually employ it, and almost never are able to use it to reach
the proper result. This is true even for those jurisdictions, such
as Louisiana and Illinois, that most frequently mention the test.
(See "Courts.") It is also true for those judges who are most strongly
identified with the test. During the five decades (1909-1961) that
Learned Hand served as a federal judge, he mentioned the test in
only eleven opinions, between 1938 and 1949. In none of these opinions
did he actually apply the test to resolve the negligence issue,
and in his last reference to the test he essentially abandoned it.
None of his fellow Second Circuit judges ever attempted to apply
the test. Similarly, neither Posner nor his like-minded colleague,
Frank Easterbrook, has been able to employ the Hand formula to resolve
the negligence issue in any case, and none of their fellow Seventh
Circuit judges has attempted to do so. (See "Myth.")
Rather than the aggregate-risk-utility test, American
and British courts apply varying standards of reasonable care, including
varying objective and subjective perspectives, that take into account
the rights and relationships among the parties. (See "Courts" and
"Myth.")
The Extent of Legal Responsibility for Tortiously
Caused Consequences ("Proximate causation," "legal causation," "remoteness,"
etc.)
In a forthcoming article, "The Grounds and Extent
of Legal Responsibility," I describe and discuss the three principal
limitations on the extent of legal responsibility for tortiously
caused harm. These limitations prevent liability when (1) the harm
almost certainly would have occurred anyway in the absence of any
tortious conduct or condition (the "no worse off" limitation), (2)
there was a superseding cause of the harm (an actual cause of the
harm that (i) intervened between the defendant's tortious conduct
and the plaintiff's injury, (ii) was a necessary ("but for") cause
of the plaintiff's injury, and (iii) was highly unexpected), or
(3) the harm did not occur as part of the realization and playing
out of one of the foreseeable risks that made the person's conduct
tortious, before the hazards created by the realization of that
risk had dissipated (the "risk-playout" limitation).
None of these three limitations match the usual academic
prescription for limiting the extent of legal responsibility for
tortiously caused harm, which would rely solely on a harm-matches-the-risk
("harm-risked") limitation that is often confused with, but which
differs significantly from, the risk-playout limitation. The results
reached by the courts are consistent with the three stated limitations
rather than the harm-risked limitation, despite the various Restatements'
efforts to install the harm-risked limitation as the sole, comprehensive
limitation on the extent of legal responsibility for tortiously
caused harm.
*******************
I welcome comments and criticisms, posted to the
list or sent to me individually.
Richard W. Wright
Professor of Law
Chicago-Kent College of Law
565 West Adams Street
Chicago, IL 60661, U.S.A.
phone: 312-906-5044
fax: 312-906-5280
Recent papers: http://ssrn.com/author=146352
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|