Date:
Tue, 24 Feb 2004 22:41:29 –0500
From:
Jason Neyers
Subject:
Loss of a Chance et al
I
post this on behalf of Ken Cooper-Stephenson:
Jason,
With
respect, you may not understand the argument. And I think you attribute
to me points I was not making. I do not wish to be misunderstood
as asserting what you suggest I am asserting. I am absolutely not
suggesting that "proving that you did not cause something [is] enough
to ground a tort that needs proof of actual causation". I was suggesting
that the so-called "material contribution" test should be restricted
to cases where there were present or potentially present two "sufficient"
causes, each of which was, or would have been, necessary without
the other. Call this NESS, if you wish. In more detail, and leaving
aside the point that Major J. in Walker eventually justified
causation on the basis of the but-for test by a finding of the (hypothetical)
fact that the proper information would have made a difference in
the conduct of the donor.
The
point is that if the donor would negligently have donated
blood even with the proper warnings, the "but-for" test cannot
be used because the donor's potential negligence is an "alternative
wrongful event" which would have been sufficient by itself to cause
the harm had the other sufficient prior cause not happened (the
negligence of the Red Cross). This does not make the donor's potential
negligence a cause of the harm, but the existence of that potential
cause in the background, means simply that the "but-for" test is
philosophically unsound as a criterion to determine whether the
negligence of the Red Cross was a cause.
Obviously
the Red Cross's conduct is an event which is one of the conditions
sufficient to result in the plaintiff's harm. It was a cause of
the harm, but not a necessary (but for) cause. In these cases the
two sufficient causes may sometimes both be considered causes (e.g.
if they occur simultaneously, or their effects strike simultaneously.
Where the causes occur sequentially, the dominant view is the "devaluation"
theory (see e.g. Fleming) so that the first cause which was sufficient
to bring about the harm on its own (necessary without the other
sufficient cause) is treated as the cause.
In
both Walker and Hollis the first sufficient cause
was the Red Cross's negligence (Walker), or the failure
of Dow to release the risk information (Hollis); and these
events meant that the second events never came about, the events
being potential negligence on the part of the donor (Walker)
or potential negligence on the part of the doctor (Hollis).
Because these alternative events would have been sufficient
(necessary without the initial negligence of Red Cross or Dow) the
but for test can not be used as the test of whether the Red Cross
or Dow's negligence was a "cause" of the harm. If the but for
test is used in such circumstances, (as La Forest rightly points
out in Hollis) there will be two sufficient negligent acts
(or potential negligent acts) and neither will be held to be the
cause of that harm: yet the plaintiff was obviously harmed by (because
of) one or other or both of these negligent acts and potential negligent
acts.
Some
other test must be used, and, for what it is worth, the courts have
called this the requirement that an event have been a "material
contribution" to the harm, being a prior event which was part of
the circumstances preceding the harm which, in the absence of the
alternative sufficient events, would have been a necessary causes).
Sorting
this all out requires much more than these few paragraphs (but may
not need the elaborate categorization of such causes which can be
found in the German literature).
Ken
From:
Jason Neyers
To: Ken Cooper-Stephenson
Subject: ODG: Loss of a Chance et al
Date: Tue, 24 Feb 2004 19:13:25 -0500
Dear
Ken,
I
understand your argument but I do not see how proving that something
was a possible alternative cause is enough to justify the decisions
in Walker and Hollis. In other words, how can proving that you did
not cause something be enough to ground a tort that needs proof
of actual causation? On the analysis you just proposed both Walker
and Hollis are wrongly decided not correctly decided (but the original
point I thought you were making was that they could be saved using
a NESS-like logic).
The
analysis proposed may prove that the defendant in those cases was
objectively naughty but this does not and should not make them civilly
liable.
--
Jason Neyers
Assistant Professor of Law
Faculty of Law
University of Western Ontario
N6A 3K7
(519) 661-2111 x. 88435
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|