Date:
Tue, 9 May 2006 18:43:49 -0500
From:
John Goldberg
Subject:
Childs v Desomeaux
Thanks,
Lewis, for the helpful "exam." My sense is that my views
are pretty close to yours, but since this is academia, I must find
a couple of hairs to split:
(1)
For these purposes, at least, Lewis seems to concede that there
is a moral obligation on the part of a social host running to users
of the roads who might be hurt by a guest who drinks too much at
the host's event. But then he points out that this is law, not morality,
which allows for the idea that the host might not be obligated for
purposes of tort liability.
I
am not hostile to this sort of distinction, but (to be a little
contrarian) I wonder if there is too much of a concession on the
first point. Sure, the phenomenon of drunk driving is a very serious
social problem. And this is why folks who drink more than a little
bit shouldn't be driving (or playing with guns, or ....). Indeed,
it's their responsibility, morally and legally, to refrain from
doing so, and they owe that responsibility to a wide range of people,
perhaps anyone they might injure by driving. And perhaps it is a
good or virtuous thing for others to mind the amounts that other
adults are drinking, at least where driving might soon ensue.
But
I don't think any of this (yet) establishes a moral duty to monitor/control
on others. And I don't say this because we here in Tennessee are
living in the wild west or the land of Nozickian libertarianism.
The issue is more subtle than that, for there are all kinds of activities
that adults undertake that pose dangers to themselves and others.
For this reason, I don't think we can casually accept the proposition
that: (i) the potential for undesirably risky conduct by actor A,
plus (ii) some form of participation in the conduct of A by B (or
some ability in B to regulate the conduct of A), (iii) suffices
to generate even a moral obligation of B to attend to A's conduct.
Suppose
adult Smith lends adult Jones a sound extension ladder. Jones then
uses it an hour later to clean the gutters on his house. Jones does
so carelessly -- say, by leaning awkwardly off of it -- and hurts
himself. (Or, if you prefer, he carelessly causes the ladder to
fall on a person who is by permission gardening in his yard so as
to injured that person.) Was Smith duty-bound to take reasonable
steps to prevent Jones's careless usage of the ladder? Was he duty-bound
to rescue or protect Jones by, say, postponing a trivial errand
(or refrain from going inside to watch the football game) so that
he could instead continue to work in his own yard and thereby monitor
Jones's use of the ladder?
(2)
I doubt that what will end up counting or not counting as misfeasance
will turn simply on the degree to which a given actor has "participated"
in the creation of a risk of harm. (And maybe Lewis was just using
that phrase as a shorthand or place-holder.) Rather, it's going
to turn on contested issues of social meaning. This was the point
of the Star Wars example from many messages ago. Thanks in part
to the activities of groups like MADD, the significance of being
a social host is changing. And it may be that there will come a
point in time, if we have not arrived there yet, where the role
of social host at a dinner party is treated as the equivalent to
that of a chaperone at a party for high-school graduates. But that
would be because we would be adopting a certain perspective on dinner
parties that differentiates them from, say, ladder-lending. To say
the same thing from another angle, the recognition of new duties
-- genuine norms of obligatory conduct as opposed to prices, or
threats of sanctions -- is to change the fabric of the relevant
form of social interaction. Such change may well be desirable, but,
again it is a reason why some courts and commentators are not content
simply to leap from the horrendousness of drunk driving, and the
potential for injuries when people drink, to the imposition of obligations
on persons other than the (competent) adult drinker.
-----Original
Message-----
From: Lewis KLAR
Sent: Tuesday, May 09, 2006 6:03 PM
Subject: RE: ODG: RE: Childs v Desomeaux
Hello:
No-one
denies that drinking and driving is a big problem in Canada, and
that we should all do something about it. Everyone feels sorry for
the victims, and everyone is a potential victim.
Okay,
now that I have got that out of the way, let us get down to tort
law.
The
problem which the Supreme Court was having with Childs is figuring
out who "created" the risk of the accident and who should
therefore have done something about it.
I
wonder if you would indulge me by considering the following exam-type
hypothetical.
"It
is A's birthday. She is turning 21. B, her friend, invites her out
to dinner to celebrate it. Two other friends, C and D, agree to
join them. C volunteers to bring two bottles of wine (it is a BYOB
restaurant). D agrees to be the designated driver. The restaurant
is "E's Fine Dining". At the restaurant, the waiter uncorks
one of the bottles. There is a corkage fee. A, B, and C all drink.
After the first bottle is finished, the waiter offers to uncork
the second bottle, they agree, and he does so. At the end of the
meal, A stands up to go to the washroom, and realizes she feels
dizzy. Evidently she has consumed a little too much wine for her
tolerance level. She sways a bit, and bangs into a chair. This is
observed by everyone, including "G", who is a diner at
another table, and by the waiter. B pays for the meal for everyone.
A declares in a slurred and loud voice that she will walk home.
No-one insists that she be accompanied or be driven home. They all
say goodnight and leave. On the way home, A because of her inebriation,
wanders onto the road, against a red light. Driver F swerves to
avoid hitting her, drives into a telephone pole, and is injured.
Driver F sues everyone."
Everyone
in this problem (including "G") could have done something
to prevent this accident. No-one did a thing. Who created the risk
of the accident? They all played a role; all by overt actions and
G by inaction.
Who
exactly would you include in the "creation of risk" role?
I assume most would exclude G. You would all of course include A.
Would you include B, C, D, and E? It all depends on your definition
of "risk creation". (To recap: B did the inviting and
paying, it was C's wine, D was the designated driver, and E served
the dinner and uncorked and poured the wine, for a fee.)
McLachlin
C.J. for the Supreme Court did not draw the line where some of us
might. But I think most are on the same page. It is just a question
of how much "participation" moves you from a by-stander
to an actor.
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|