Date:
Fri, 7 Jul 2006 15:33:35 -0400
From:
John Swan
Subject:
Intangible Injuries for Breach of Contract (Fidler v. Sun Life)
Andrew,
Leaving
aside the question of where, i.e., in what kinds of contractual
relations, damages for intangible injuries will be awarded under
the Supreme Court of Canada’s new approach, I think that a
plaintiff will still have to show that he or she suffered some kind
of non-pecuniary loss. Lord Denning’s catalogue of the deprivations,
not to mention the sore feet, which Mr. Jarvis suffered, provides
a basis for saying that it was at least reasonable for Mr. Jarvis
to have suffered lost enjoyment. The more interesting argument is
that of Lord Mustill in Ruxley who says that ignoring the
disappointment and annoyance that Mr. Forsyth suffered is simply
not acceptable and the £2,500 awarded is just some balm for
the wound. Presumably courts are well-equipped to judge whether
the loss suffered is sufficiently serious to warrant compensation.
(When a friend of mine asked what she could expect as damages for
lost enjoyment arising from the fact that the DJ she had hired failed
to show up for her wedding, I asked her, "How well can you
weep in the witness box?". She said that she could do a most
impressive job. I encouraged her to sue and she ended up with $1,500;
about three times what she would have paid the DJ. (Would it have
mattered if her husband had engaged the DJ.?)
Having
thought about Fidler v. Sun Life a bit more, one of my
concerns is that it individualizes or risks the individualization
of too many contractual relations. If damages are indeed based on
what the defendant can foresee, then sellers can’t treat their
buyers as a group. Sellers who sell to a multitude of buyers cannot
easily, if at all, be expected to have the terms of their contracts
or the consequences of breach vary in accordance with the mental
balance of their customers. It’s better to tell the psychologically
fragile or choleric, unincorporated business person that his idiosyncratic
feelings will not be recognized by the law than to face the costs
— ultimately huge costs — of giving him balm for his
wounded feelings. Of course, it’s a policy decision, just
as it is a policy decision not to allow pre- or post-judgment interest
rates to reach the rate that would actually compensate the plaintiff
for being denied the money due to it: We do it because (i) uniformity
saves costs and (ii) it all works out in the end—today’s
disappointed plaintiff may be tomorrow’s defendant caught
between a rock and hard place and forced to breach a contract. Throwing
more money into the pool and having it sloshing around between people
competing to demonstrate hurt feelings does not seem to be likely
to improve anything.
The
point that I made about the so-called second rule in Hadley
v. Baxendale has to be seen in the context of the concern that
contracts not be too individualized — I’m not liable
for your loss, regardless of what you tell me (and what I may now
foresee if I breach our deal), because I won’t accept that
risk. This is why cases which allow the mere communication of the
consequences of the loss to increase the defendant’s damages
are so bad: they permit the almost complete individualization of
the defendant’s contracts in circumstances over which the
defendant has no control and moreover, individualization in circumstances
in which, had the defendant had the chance to deal with the plaintiff’s
particular circumstances, it would have asked for more money or
told the plaintiff to deal with that problem itself. It’s
not clear to me what the Supreme Court’s views on this issue
are.
The
beauty of the Jarvis v. Swan Tours, Ruxley and
Farley v. Skinner approaches was that they had built-in
limits on both the scope of aggravated damages and the amount. Tour
operators now simply treat claims for lost enjoyment as a cost of
doing business and they will only engage their insurers when the
amount exceeds their self-insurance limit or the deductible. If
those damages become potentially huge, the whole structure of the
industry will have to change and it’s hard to see how giving
huge damages to a small number of people will help in the long-run.
It’s not good public policy to increase the incentives to
sue.
The
problem that those of us who have to think about damages for breach
of contract now is "How do you integrate into a discussion
of damages for breach of contract based on the compensation principle
(and thousands of cases) the Supreme Court’s idea that Hadley
v. Baxendale is the source of the defendant’s liability?"
It’s an over-statement, but not by as much as it should be,
to say that it’s a bit like working with two incompatible
theories, never knowing which one will be applied in the particular
case.
John
-----Original
Message-----
From: Andrew Tettenborn
Sent: July 3, 2006 4:50 AM
Subject: [Fwd: RE: ODG: Intangible Injuries for Breach of Contract
(Fidler v. Sun Life)]
Thanks
to John for pointing out a number of the problems in the reasoning
in Fidler, and why the best school report we can give
it is "could do much better." John's spot-on when he
says that we can't just reduce non-pecuniary damages to a Hadley
question.
Indeed,
the Fidler difficulties on this score go further. The SCC had
to deal with the general acceptance that you can't get non-pecuniaries
in commercial cases, and did it by saying "Oh well, distress
etc won't be foreseeable there." The trouble is, it sometimes
will be (e.g. the facts in Hayes v James & Charles Dodd
[1990] 2 All ER 815, where solicitors cock up a lease of commercial
premises to a sole trader so he can't use them and understandably
gets depressed). What do we do here? Unless we want to give non-pecuniaries,
which seems counterintuitive, it seems that what the SCC is really
saying is that distress is regarded as, or deemed
to be, non-foreseeable. But it's not hard to see that this begs
the question and takes us back to the "pleasure contracts
- other contracts" distinction they've just been at pains
to trash.
Just
one small problem does strike me about John's view, however. John
candidly, and absolutely correctly, says that non-pecuniaries
are conventional: as witness cases like Ruxley, the court
is not concerned with the actual amount of distress, anger, etc
that the plaintiff suffers (or, for that matter, doesn't suffer).
But if so, and if here (unlike compensation for all other kinds
of afflictions) the plaintiff doesn't have to show he's personally
suffered anything, then the "putting the plaintiff in the
position he/she would have been in" analysis begins to look
a bit threadbare. That's why I'm reaching the view that damages
of this sort are a matter of a more abstract process of valuing
the interest of the plaintiff that's been infringed, rather than
compensating for distress in the same way we compensate for a
lost sale or broken leg.
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|