Date:
Fri, 19 Dec 2003 09:48:28 –0600
From:
Ken Cooper-Stephenson
Subject:
Mitigation by adoption
I
absolutely agree with Andrew. In my view this was well addressed
about 20 years ago by the English Court of Appeal (I think in Emeh).
(1)
Mitigation is, as Andrew states, the unreasonable failure
to minimize, or exacerbation of, the potential losses. Once it has
been held not to be unreasonable for a mother (or the parents) to
keep a child, mitigation does not arise.
(2)
the concept of "unreasonableness" is more subjective in the context
of mitigation than it is for defendant liability: to some extent,
a defendant takes the plaintiff as she or he is found, and this
includes her religious and cultural beliefs (see, e.g. Janiak
in Canada), and also the essay by Guido Calabresi in Ideals,
Beliefs, Attitudes and the Law (1985).
(3)
if you apply the risk, benefit, burden, social utility equation,
it will (almost always, if not always) come down in favour of the
mother/parents, because what they are doing is socially useful,
and, more importantly, for them as, they have demonstrated,
the burden of precautions involves putting her/their child up for
adoption is too great.
(4)
in my view, the position taken by Gaudron has an important feminist
underpinning, although it is not exclusively a gender matter: The
description of "bonding" during pregnancy by Taylor J. in the B.C.
case of Fredette, where he refused to consider the failure
by a very young plaintiff to put her unplanned twins up for adoption
as either a novus actus, a failure to mitigate, or contributorily
negligent. Women may very well often have a different perspective
on this issue, because many of them have carried a child (their
child) to term for nine months, and their early life experiences
tend to focus on mother-child relationships more so than the early
childhood experiences of men (although, again, not exclusively).
And
(5)
I absolutely agree that! this is a duty of care issue, and it is
a matter of distributive just ice, and said so in my essay in Tort
Theory (1993). To me, the idea in McFarlane
that it is distributively fair to burden the mother or parents
with the cost of the upbringing of an unplanned child rather than
the person who negligently caused the child to be conceived
or born, is extraordinary. The question, as a duty of care matter,
is accurately described as a distributive determination; and in
my view it will usually be properly answered in favour of the (innocent)
plaintiff. Of course, corrective justice has no way of solving this
issue. If one were to apply notions of corrective justice as the
sole philosophical underpinning of tort law, the solution would
be very simple. the wrong should be corrected. Corrective justice
has no criteria for excluding the losses from this kind of negligence
from the purview o
The
plaintiffs in these cases have been put by the negligent defendant
into the unchosen position of having to make difficult and extremely
onerous unplanned choices concerning their life-plans concerning
both personal and financial interests. These choices should have
been theirs to make, and should not have been thrust on them
by a negligent defendant .... in my view.
As
to off-setting advantages, this is a more difficult question. However
in Personal Injury Damages in Canada 2nd ed. (1996), I suggest
a wide range of situations involving "Overlap of Heads and Reduced
Need" (Chapter 8, pp 533-562), including some where non-pecuniary
advantages might arguably be set off against pecuniary losses, although
I see that that is an arguable point, particularly since the amount
of non-pecuniary damages is arbitrary, or, in Canada, at least,
influenced by concerns of distributive justice (that society cannot
afford to pay more than approx. $300,00 even to a quadriplegic plaintiff
- see Andrews for the reasons of Dickson J.
I myself think that the damages in a wrongful birth case should
reflect both pecuniary and non-pecuniary harm, and that specific
to each case they should be the amount of financial compensation
which will enable the plaintiff or plaintiffs to progress with their
life-plan with as similar degree of life-fulfillment (happiness
or well-being, if you wish) as they might have expected absent the
unchosen birth. Sometimes, by awarding a significant part of
the cost of raising the child, the plaintiff(s) will be put into
a situation in which, balancing the good with the bad, they are
as happy as they would have been without the child.
In
a way, a proper damages assessment may serve to much better solve
a (rather blinkered) seemingly all-or-nothing conclusion at the
duty of care or novus actus stages of analysis.
Just
a few thoughts on my part! I may find myself making some extended
comments on other portions of the dialogue of the ODG over the past
few months, in which, because of time pressures, I was unable to
engage.
My
well-wishes to all.
Ken Cooper-Stephenson,
From:
Andrew Robertson
Subject: ODG: Mitigation by adoption
Date: Thu, 11 Dec 2003 12:29:40 +1100
The
point I was (too briefly) trying to make yesterday is that it
is wrong to see the availability of adoption as a mitigation issue.
The crucial issue in these cases is the anterior question whether
the cost of raising a healthy child is a harm against which the
law of negligence should provide protection. Once that question
is answered in the affirmative, there is no warrant for reducing
the plaintiff's damages on the basis of a failure to mitigate
by adoption.
I
am not suggesting that 'mitigation is unreasonable' as Jason puts
it, but that, in the absence of unreasonable behaviour by the
plaintiff, no question of mitigation arises. Jason asks whether
'one might then ask the plaintiff to mitigate in the normal way
if they now find being a parent unappealing.' The plaintiff may
not be suing (and indeed may not have sought sterilisation) because
she finds being a parent unappealing, but because she finds that
having an additional child is unaffordable. Cattenach exemplifies
this point.
The
statement to which Gaudron J was responding in the quote Harold
circulated yesterday was that of Meagher JA in CES v Superclinics
(Aust) Pty Ltd 38 NSWLR 47, 87:
'The
law ordains that a plaintiff must mitigate her damages. In the
present context, why does that not require the mother to put
the child of which she vociferously complains out to adoption?
Why should the law treat seriously her claim for the recovery
of expenses which she does not need to occur.'
This
misconceives the mitigation principle. The law does not ordain
that the plaintiff mitigate her damages. It reduces her damages
award if the defendant is able to convince the court that the
plaintiff has exacerbated her loss by behaving unreasonably after
the breach has occurred. I take unreasonableness to mean a socially
unacceptable loss-enhancing response to the situation in which
the plaintiff finds herself post-breach. My point is that the
decision to keep and raise a child who has been accidentally conceived
is sufficiently common (if I might be permitted a little 'armchair
empiricism'!) that I don't see how it could be construed as socially
unacceptable or unreasonable behaviour. The plaintiff does not
need to invoke any 'life is special' argument to avoid a reduction
of damages for failure to mitigate because it is for the defendant
to show that the plaintiff has unreasonably exacerbated the loss
for which the defendant is liable. That is a difficult burden
to discharge, and rightly so because if it had not been for the
defendant's breach the plaintiff would not find herself having
to make the difficult decision which the defendant now seeks to
second-guess.
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|