Date:
Sat, 8 Jul 2006 13:52:45 -0400
From:
David Cheifetz
Subject:
Intangible Injuries for Breach of Contract (Fidler v. Sun Life)
Adam,
Fidler
claims that insurance contracts are different from
some, but not necessarily all, contracts of the type the court describes
as "normal" commercial contracts. See paragraphs 45 and
46.
According
to the court, insurance contracts have this psychological benefits.
The class of "normal" commercial contracts don't have
necessarily have, but may on the evidence be found to contain, the
psychological benefit. (Let's not even begin to ask how that will
fit in with the other Canadian "rules" for interpreting
insurance polices, which are based on the premise that, for interpretation
purposes, there is nothing intrinsically unique about insurance
contracts.) Or is this some sort of self-contained difference which
has no effect on other rules for interpreting insurance policies?
It
seems to me that what paras 45-46 assert is that, on an objective
basis, there is now a presumption that this psychological benefit
is an object of insurance policies. However, there is no such presumption
"normal" commercial contracts: a term which the panel
didn't define, "normal" so frequently used in normal commercial
matters that there was no need to define it, since its the meaning
is so-well settled that no qualified judge, competent lawyer, or
informed lay person - or even the proverbial moron in a hurry -
would have any doubt about what is or isn't a "normal"
commercial contract.
Just
so nobody needs to go looking for the paragraphs.
45
It does not follow, however, that all mental distress associated
with a breach of contract is compensable. In normal commercial contracts,
the likelihood of a breach of contract causing mental distress is
not ordinarily within the reasonable contemplation of the parties.
It is not unusual that a breach of contract will leave the wronged
party feeling frustrated or angry. The law does not award damages
for such incidental frustration. The matter is otherwise, however,
when the parties enter into a contract, an object of which is to
secure a particular psychological benefit. In such a case, damages
arising from such mental distress should in principle be recoverable
where they are established on the evidence and shown to have been
within the reasonable contemplation of the parties at the time the
contract was made. The basic principles of contract damages do not
cease to operate merely because what is promised is an intangible,
like mental security.
46
This conclusion is supported by the policy considerations that
have led the law to eschew damages for mental suffering in commercial
contracts. As discussed above, this reluctance rests on two policy
considerations – the minimal nature of the mental suffering
and the fact that in commercial matters, mental suffering on breach
is "not in the contemplation of the parties as part of the
business risk of the transaction": McGregor on Damages,
at p. 63. Neither applies to contracts where promised mental security
or satisfaction is part of the risk for which the parties contracted.
Maybe
all the panel meant is that, by definition, a "normal"
commercial contract is one in which a psychological benefit isn't
an object. That could be the implication of paragraph 46. So, we've
now been told that any vacation contracts, indeed any contract which
clearly has a peace of mind component (or some other psychological
benefit) by definition isn't a "normal" contract.
In
passing, who wants to start keep the list of the rules for the interpretation
of "normal" contract rules of interpretation that won't
apply to the interpretation of contracts which are not within the
class?
Anyway,
what we now have Canada is one example of a rule of interpretation
for contracts such as insurance policies which aren't "normal"
commercial contracts and another rule for contracts which are "normal"
commercial contracts. This is an untapped field for scholarship
which, coincidentally, will be analyzed in the forthcoming Canadian
text book: The Law of Normal and Abnormal Contracts in Canada,
"M. Python" ed. (Oz, Walamaloo Press, 2009). I gather
the text is being written in association with one or more of the
academics listed here.
Or, at least it will be once they're weaned off the sheep-dip.
In
the meantime, we practitioners will have to start keeping a checklist
of what contracts are normal and what aren't. And a sub-list of
what may have been normal at inception but may become something
other than normal later. You may well be right that, ultimately,
Fidler can be massaged into coherency. For now, though,
Canadian lawyers have to deal with its incoherent aspects.
Best,
David
-----Original
Message-----
From: Adam Kramer
Sent: July 8, 2006 11:30 AM
To: 'John Swan'
Subject: RE: [Fwd: RE: ODG: Intangible Injuries for Breach of Contract
(Fidler v. Sun Life)]
John,
I
agree that the application by the SCC of their test suggests that
they are not looking much beyond foreseeability, however what they
said (albeit not entirely consistently or sufficiently fleshed out)
can lead to a coherent principle. The Hadley v Baxendale
test does unite damages under a single principle as the single and
controlling test (paragraphs 54 to 55 of the judgment) if it is
understood as incorporating not just foreseeability but also acceptance
of risk, which, as you rightly intimate, must be the basis of the
remoteness rule. The reference to restoring the parties "to
the position they contracted for" (paragraph 44 of the judgment)
and the reference to the Jarvis/Farley test of
psychological benefit (an ugly term that) being "an object"
of the contract (paragraphs 45 and 47 of the judgment) indicates
that we’re not talking about mere sine qua non causation (what
position would I have been in) or foreseeability, but must also
be talking about acceptance of risk (which is what I’ve always
understood the "object of the contract" test to be about):
see paragraph 46 and the emphasis on "the risk for which the
parties contracted". The continuation of the traditional focus
on "contemplation" rather than foreseeability leaves room
for such a test.
I
would say that this decision, properly understood, allows the rehabilitation
of Hadley v Baxendale, i.e. the remoteness test, as a test
of assumption of risk. The foreseeability test is the best rule
of thumb, along with others (such as presumptions that in commercial
dealings the only "objects" of the contract, i.e. risks
accepted, are commercial ones), and all together we have the acceptance
test which nicely fits under the term "reasonable contemplation",
properly understood. As you already know, I do my best to make this
point in an article last year which I’ve already plugged in
this mailing list, last time we talked about remoteness ("An
Agreement-Centred Approach to Remoteness and Contract Damage"
in N Cohen and E McKendrick (editors), Comparative Remedies
for Breach of Contract (Oxford, Hart Publishing, 2005) 249-286
- if my computer skills are up to it then there should be a hyperlink
to the article in this sentence), and I have a go at mental distress
along the above lines in there.
As
for the point about individualisation, I also try to address that
in my article: the gist being that when you’re dealing with
a standardized vendor you know his prices and insurance are already
fixed so can’t expect him to accept individualised risks,
and therefore can tell him about yourself until you’re blue
in the face and still his risks will not be affected (because you
could not reasonably understand him to have accepted any risks when
you told him). However you can also understand the vendor to have
taken and spread broad types of foreseeable risk within his generally
fixed price and insurance, and so many risks will have been accepted.
So
I think that my view is that the SCC is getting to the right test,
although spoils it somewhat by, in paragraph 56, paying only lip-service
to that test. As David observes, what is special about this insurance
contract? Indeed, in what commercial contract in which the other
side undertakes to make payments upon the occurrence of certain
events or circumstances (i.e. just about every commercial contract)
is one not contracting "for benefits that are both tangible,
such as payments, and intangible, such as knowledge of income security"
(paragraph 56 of the judgment). Contracts are all about income security.
The point is that the intangible peace of mind that comes from income
security is not one of the objects of most commercial contracts,
i.e. one of the risks assumed by the promisor. I’m not saying
that the decision is wrong, but I think the question needed investigating
a little more to tease out the special features of disability insurance
etc.
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|