![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
If the time has come for systems of law as 'well-developed'
as our own to do away with fictitious presumptions as a means of determining
whether to award subrogation (per Lord Hoffmann in BFC v Parc), the same
must also be true of resulting trusts. Fictions are not so easily avoided. After all, any commercial contract
case is likely to involve at least three fictions just for starters :
that companies are people, that these "people" have intentions, and that
what is written in the contract documents can be taken as good evidence
of those "intentions". (If both parties are companies, then of course
each fiction must be applied twice, taking us up to 6 fictions per case.)
If resulting trust doctrine can get by with just one fiction per case,
I think it is doing pretty well. Any proposal to re-state the law without
the fiction can be taken on its own merits.
Of course, it is a sad thing if the law regularly has to pretend that
something is so when it isn't, as where (to use a famous example) an Oxford
college has to pretend that the Dean's dog is really a cat, to evade the
rule against dogs in college. But it is different where we are talking
not about ascertainable facts (such as whether a particular beast is a
dog or a cat), but rather about the applicability of the law's own concepts
(such as "whether there is a contract") or about practically unascertainable
facts (such as what someone's intention was). There, it is not so obvious
that fictions are objectionable. Surely the point at which we need to
register objection is only when someone has forgotten that the fiction
*is* a fiction.
Steve Hedley
=================================================== <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |