![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Some further comments
on what is obvious and what is a claim in unjust enrichment.
The Archer example (I learn, incidentally, from reading German papers
at my temporary home in Munich, that he remains a Lord, but no longer
a member of the conservative fraction in the UK's upper chamber) is a
good illustration for the various models of classifying unjust enrichment
claims and how they interact with other areas of the law.
What is obvious to anyone but a lunatic, as Steve Hedley puts it, is
that the money paid under the judgment which now turns out to be based
on false and apparently fabricated facts, should be returned - at least
if the judgment is reversed. I agree that this looks obvious, but not
much more obvious that if the government requires the payment of taxes
which later are found not to be exigible it must pay them back. It took
the House of Lords to sort out in Woolwich Building Society v IRC that
these overpaid taxes can be claimed back, and English law was fairly hostile
towards such a claim before the House of Lords ruled otherwise.
Peter Birks reminds us that the law of gravity was discovered because
somebody (Isaac Newton, if I am not mistaken) no longer thought it obvious
that an apple, once detached from a tree, falls to the ground. Law is
more culturally charged than physics. In law, usually, anything which
is "obvious" has a base in beliefs which are widely shared within a given
population, but which may be considered "lunatic" by a different population.
It is obvious in the UK that any person has the right to change his or
her name by title deed. It is obvious in Germany that this is impermissible
and would lead to chaos, a rise in the crime rate, and the downfall of
occidental society in general.
So, the "obvious" in law is usually consensus. If we are lucky, we discover
a rational reason behind such consensus which allow us to distinguish,
particularly in less "obvious" cases, between claims which should be allowed
and those which should not.
Now back to Archer. I suppose that in all those societies from which
we have received contributions to this debate people would generally agree
that under the assumed circumstances Lord Archer should give the money
back to the Daily Star - certainly if the judgment is overturned. But
would they agree on why it should be given back? I think the easiest explanation
is "because he should not have got it in the first place". This may or
may not be coupled with sentiments of "because he cheated".
The condictio indebiti follows the first explanation.
It allows for the recovery of an enrichment made at another person's expense
which is not supported by a valid legal ground, and has no problem in
turning the seemingly obvious into a legal claim. But the simplest explanations
are not always the best, and are not always simple if looked at from a
different angle. If we return to physics: the geocentric explanation that
the sun and the planets move around the earth looks simpler from the perspective
of a person on the earth looking at the sun than the heliocentric explanation.
The same geocentric explanation, however, creates terrible problems when
looking at the complicated cycles and epicycles which the planets appear
to pursue from the viewpoint of the earth. (Present wisdom has it, at
any rate, that the sun and all planets rotate around each other, although
this is not noticed much in the movement of the sun because of its large
mass.)
The law of unjust enrichment is highly interlinked with other areas of
the law and can wreak considerable havoc on them by allowing or not allowing
a claim. The contractual rule that a contract for the performance of an
illegal act (beating up another person) becomes irrelevant if the thug,
after having beaten up the victim, can claim a quantum meruit. The procedural
rule that a judgment is final after all possibilities of appeal have been
exhausted becomes equally irrelevant if we allow unjust enrichment claims
to return payments made under this judgment while leaving the judgment
itself intact.
The condictio indebiti approach functions in a legal
system which has written its substantive law (contract in particular,
but also property) with a view towards something like a general unjust
enrichment action. Somebody agrees to help a friend to paint his rooms,
and after having fallen out with the friend, claims a quantum meruit.
No problem in continental legal systems which have gratuitous contracts
for work or services which give a valid legal cause for keeping the enrichment.
The requirement of an unjust factor protects the recipient of the help
in English law where there is no such gratuitous contract. The "friend"
cannot claim under mistake, because he was not mistaken, nor under failure
of consideration, because no consideration was to be expected. The combination
of a condictio indebiti with the lack of gratuitous contracts is more
problematic.
Likewise, in continental legal systems, form requirements will often
contain an additional provision which will validate a transaction once
it has been completed without observance of this form - namely, in order
to prevent unjust enrichment from undoing a contract which has been fully
performed. English statutory form requirements will not always have such
a similar rule - traditionally, once such a transaction was completed,
it could not be undone by actions for money had and received, or for quantum
meruit, because this always required a specific ground or unjust factor.
Similar problems arise within gaming and betting contracts. The combination
of a prohibitory norm and a condictio indebiti means that a disappointed
gambler can claim back his or her stake. A condictio indebiti approach
requires a contractual rule which defends a completed gaming or betting
transaction against unjust enrichment claims - e.g., by making this a
"non-actionable" contract.
This is why I think that, in English law, it is not helpful to resort
to either "the obvious", or a very broad "failure of basis", or the condictio
indebiti, to explain why Archer should give the money back - this creates
a host of problems elsewhere (I would be interested to hear from our Canadian
colleagues, though, how Canadian law copes with all these problems). I
said in my last contribution that restitution for wrongs looks like the
best bet. Another avenue, though, would be to modify the "illegitimate"
requirement for compulsion to allow for the illegitimate use of a perfectly
legal or legitimate means in order to pursue a claim which, under the
given facts, was without merit. Broadening compulsion (as suggested by
Jonathon Moore) would help English law to cope with some cases where it
has so far distributed rather harsh justice.
Gerhard Dannemann <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |