![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Dear everyone
I have enjoyed the useful exchanges over the Great Peace
case, and am looking forward to reading the case more closely. I'd like
to add a few points, mostly by way of agreement with what others have
said. But some consequences worry me, and I'd be interested to know whether
they worry others too.
I agree the notion of "equitable mistake" - though it
had justifiable policy aims - was always something of a muddle from a
strictly jurisdictional point of view. There are so many parallels between
frustration and mistake, that it seems odd that equity can intervene in
the one case but not the other. The consequences of that view, as expressed
in para 76, seem to me to be quite disastrous, but that is another matter.
So I am happy to follow Steve Hedley's path a certain
distance. "Mistake" and Frustration" perform similar functions, the one
relating to events existing at the time of the contract, the other relating
to events occurring after that time. A useful example is the contract
for construction of a tunnel. Suppose the contractors unexpectedly strike
rock where they thought there would be clay. It's much too expensive to
shift at the agreed contract price. You could deal with this either as
an existing event (the state of the ground) or a future one (what they
would encounter along the way). Without suggesting there is any right
answer to the example, it has always seemed to me to make little sense
if you get a different result, depending solely on whether you appeal
to the law of frustration or the law of mistake. But I am not so sure
about Steve's comments about the way it all depends on the fact that "the
parties' agreement embodied an assumption". This harks back to a very
old (and in my view rather finickity) debate, about whether mistake is
simply a matter of contract interpretation. The practical side is, of
course, that no court would think of holding in favour of mistake or frustration,
without a most anxious consideration of the terms of the contract. But
what if the court is left genuinely in doubt, about whether there was
a "embodied assumption" over a state of affairs X (existing or future),
which, almost by definition, neither side has focussed their minds on?
Or suppose, though both parties independently thought X when Y was true,
they never discussed it so that it wasn't present in the "matrix" of fact
common to their negotiation? In either event there is, I suspect, no "embodied
assumption" yet a court would - and I think should - intervene once it
becomes apparent that the contract will work out much worse than the parties
had expected.
The "common assumption" and "mistake" themes are thus
complementary approaches, rather than theoretical alternatives. So it
seems to me that writers and judges use symbols - the ideas of "mistake"
and "impossibility" - which provide a starting point from "outside" the
four corners of the contract. If we discover that both parties have made
the same mistake or prediction, or simply haven't thought about it at
all (even though - objectively speaking - it needed attention) then that
is a start. Then we look at the contract. If it is totally silent on the
point, and after we have considered the basic objectives of the contract,
we still think the point is "fundamental" to the parties' aspirations
for their contract, then we can say it's likely that the Court will grant
relief. I may be wrong, and the point I am making looks like a precious
one. But it seems to me that it can make a difference, so that neither
doctrine is confined to a "narrow ambit" - I don't like that at all!
Paul Michalik was kind enough to inject NZ's Contractual
Mistakes Act 1977 into the discussion. I am still prepared to admit some
responsibility for what the Act contains, and to defend it in its moments
of peril. In section 6(1), it follows the philosophy I have described.
To me, though, the key thing about the Act is the much more flexible remedies
it provides in section 7. They are more varied than those available even
under the Solle v Butcher ruling. I think I can say that the hope was
that courts would be more open to giving relief, once they could use the
remedial provisions to alleviate any hardship that might be suffered by
the party insisting on the contract. Unfortunately, the Law Reform Committee
that drafted the legislation could not be prevailed upon to specify the
principles on which that remedial discretion would be exercised. Had it
done so, that might have clarified the scope of the discretion, and helped
with subsequent difficulties over the interpretation of section 6 as well.
Could I conclude with a brief additional comment on the
vexed problem of "misprediction"? I agree with Steve that it seems unprincipled,
in the present context, to raise a distinction between mistake and misprediction.
Nor is it useful to ask whether the mistake related to something whose
truth or otherwise could have been discovered at the time of the contract.
And also, with him, I don't think all this means that the law of restitution
and the law of contract are irreconcilable, but I suspect my reasons for
thinking this may differ from his.
The problem, it seems to me, lies the use of the "misprediction"
doctrine as a bar to recovery in the law of mistaken payments. Let us
take as an example the case of A, who receives a bill from B Co , and
he is not sure whether it is really due. He rings up B Co, and they tell
him, "We believe this bill is correct, but unfortunately our computers
have been out for week and there's no way of checking your query at the
moment". A, who is a meticulous about paying his bills on the 20th of
the month, says to himself, "I'll pay this now and if there's anything
wrong, I'm sure they'll give me a credit on next month's bill." And, when
it turns out that there's been a mistake, they do. But surely it can't
be right to say B Co could have kept A's money if it wanted? It is just
not true to say that A has "taken a risk", or "done what he set out to
do", when he has acted on a bill which would not have been issued if the
true facts had been known. In this case (with Steve) I think "common assumption"
analysis works better than Duncan Sheehan's "mistake vs misprediction"
analysis. Nor can I see how Duncan's latest suggestion (that there's a
difference between completed and uncompleted transactions) gets around
this problem, because on its face the payment is complete when A makes
it. But (unlike Steve) I think the notion of "mistake" should be widened
to cover this type of situation too.
My worry is that if the misprediction doctrine is implausible
in the contract setting, it is just as likely not to work in the mistaken
payment setting either, as I think my example shows. In both cases the
doctrine substitutes a purely temporal criterion, for a much more complex
inquiry into policy and principle. The Clarion case is one such example
- it didn't, on my reading , turn simply on the question of misprediction,
but rather on the fact that the mistake was about the effect of the agreement
the parties were making (cf NZ's CMA, s 6(2)(a)). And the recent judicial
- and august - support for the misprediction doctrine in the Dextra
case was unnecessary for the decision, and doesn't, unfortunately, make
the doctrine any the more workable. I have my own views on this which
I hope will soon appear in print, but I'd be interested in whether others
think it might be an open question.
Sorry this has turned out so long-winded!
Richard Sutton <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |