![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Stimulated by Rob’s comments I have a few further
thoughts about the case:
(1) The "cause of action" issue: does English
law recognise a restitutionary claim for tax paid under a mistake of law?
I share Rob’s view that the CA's
treatment of this issue was weak and unconvincing. Jonathan Parker LJ’s
methodology was very strange. However, it doesn’t follow from the
fact that the CA did a poor job that no respectable arguments can be marshalled
to support the proposition that recovery of ultra vires tax payments should
be governed by an 'exclusive regime'. The public character of tax authorities,
and the special nature of the relationship between citizen and state,
might lead one to conclude that such claims are sufficiently different
from claims between private individuals that they should be fenced off
and treated differently. Rebecca Williams has developed this line of thought
more eloquently and expertly than I can manage, and I'm not sure that
I find it completely convincing: it troubles me, for example, that the
public/private borderline is so fuzzy that cases would often arise where
it was unclear whether or not the claim fell within the scope of an exclusive
regime. Without pursuing this any further, though, I would just say that
it may not be entirely fair to counsel for the IRC to suggest that they
relied solely on the CA's narrow textual approach: at [131]ff Lord Walker
indicates that arguments from principle were also made, albeit that he
and the others seem to have found these unconvincing.
(2) The "mistake" issue: did DMG make the payments
of ACT under a mistake of law?
(a) Do judicial decisions changing the law retrospectively
render payments made in line with the old law mistaken?
The HL were obliged to say yes in light of KB
v Lincoln. In my view, however, the majority’s reasoning
in KB was deeply flawed because the reach of legal fictions cannot
be determined by taking them at face value and discovering in them an
'inherent logic' which they do not possess. In KB the majority
started with the fiction that the effect of a case reversing a previous
decision is retrospectively to make the law governing the relationship
between the parties different from the law which actually governed their
relationship at the time when they entered it. It can be argued that this
fiction is defensible because without it, the court could not adjust the
parties’ relationship in a way that ex hypothesi the court now considers
appropriate; moreover, litigants would otherwise have no incentive to
press for changes to the law, as they would be unable to take personal
advantage of such changes. But these reasons do not necessarily hold good
when it asked whether the fiction of retrospective legal change also affects
the relationship between other people who were not parties to the case.
If the pursuer in Donoghue had had an auntie who paid her money
because she felt sorry for her and correctly believed at the time when
she made the gift that the pursuer had no claim in tort against the defender,
the question whether the auntie should be allowed to recover the money
because she should retrospectively be deemed to have made a mistake can
be sensibly answered only by starting from first principles: it won't
do simply to say 'one fiction fits all' and that the auntie must have
been mistaken because retrospective changes to the law must affect everybody
if they are going to affect anybody. But if the majority in KB
had a better reason than this for its findings on retrospective mistakes
then I can’t find them; nor can I find anything in DMG
which makes me feel better, notwithstanding Lord Hoffmann's attempt to
cheer me up at [23] by saying that the mistake in a retrospective mistake
case is a 'deemed' mistake. I guessed that! The question is why should
the claimant be deemed to have made a mistake? Answer: 'practical considerations
of fairness'. Hey ho.
(b) Was DMG mistaken in its belief that the money was
due?
I agree with Rob that this was the IRC's best point and
that counsel seems to have blown it. As Lord Scott holds (and as Monica
Chowdry and I observed in [2005] RLR 1, at 16-18) DMG was not mistaken
in its belief that a taxpayer which failed to make a group income election
was liable to pay ACT: its mistake was to think that it was not entitled
to make such an election. This mistake led DMG not to make an election,
with the inexorable result that the money was due. This suggests that
DMG's mistake was neither here nor there and that it shouldn’t have
been allowed to recover. Otherwise a taxpayer who pays money pursuant
to a completely valid tax regime might just as well say 'Oh I didn’t
realise that if I put my assets offshore I wouldn’t have had to
pay this tax, so now that my friendly accountant has explained this to
me I should be entitled to a rebate because I paid under a mistake'.
At first instance Park J recognised the problem at [25]
but sought to get round it by holding that DMG 'would have made' an election
if it had known that it was entitled to do so, and then asserting that
it followed from this that the money wasn't due. This was a non sequitur.
In the CA Jonathan Parker LJ mistook the facts when he held at [231] that
'the regime gave rise to no obligation to pay' because it was unlawful
the only bit of the statute which was unlawful was the bit which disabled
DMG from making an election; DMG's liability to pay MCT in the event that
it failed to make an election arose under a statutory section that was
not unlawful at all. In the HL Lord Hoffmann agrees with Jonathan Parker
LJ at [32] and is wrong for the same reason. He also dismisses Park J's
recognition of the problem as 'rather sophisticated', a criticism echoed
by Lord Walker at [143] ('over-analytical'). Given the general expertise
in tax law which they both undoubtedly possess (especially Lord Walker)
I find this language surprising; they would have done better to heed the
philosopher’s advice endorsed by Lord Hope at [41]: 'Seek simplicity
and distrust it.' However, at [62] while Lord Hope correctly rejects Jonathan
Parker LJ's analysis, he also agrees with Park J, and is wrong for the
same reason: the fact that there was 'an unbroken causative link between
the mistake and the payment' is true, but it still doesn’t mean
that the payment wasn’t due (as Lord Scott correctly observes at
[89]).
So I agree with Rob that much more should have been made
of this - but still, I wonder whether there isn’t an answer which
the majority of the HL might have given in response to Lord Scott - namely
that the English courts were required by the ECJ in Metallgesellschaft
at [96] to award restitution to parties in DMG's position in order to
give full effect to its Article 52 rights, and that this direction mandated
a departure from the rule that normally governs restitutionary claims
in unjust enrichment, that they are debarred by the existence of valid
statutory rules requiring the claimant to pay the defendant. I’m
afraid that my EC law isn't good enough to answer this question, but perhaps
there is someone out there who knows the answer: where a statutory tax
regime is made up of several interconnected sections, some of which are
expressly declared void for incompatibility with the Treaty, but some
of which are not, can an English court override the tax authority's right
to keep money paid under one of the surviving valid sections on the basis
that one of the void sections would otherwise be indirectly effective,
contrary to the declaration of incompatibility? (At [82] Lord Scott indicates
that the answer is 'no'!)
Charles
At 17:30 25/10/2006 +0100, Robert Stevens
wrote: A first response to DMG.
(1) Unsurprisingly, I think Lord Scott,
a judge I have always held in the highest esteem, gets it right.
That said, I think counsel for the
Revenue dropped the ball. Badly. It seems to have been conceded by counsel
that a claim for restitution was available but only under Woolwich
(see Lord Hoffmann at [7], Lord Walker at [117], [135]). Lord Scott
seems to have taken the view he did without the assistance of argument
on the point.
Normally, it is a good tactic when
seeking to resist an appeal to the House of Lords to simply maintain
that the Court of Appeal were right for the reasons they gave. However,
in this case the arguments for an 'exclusive regime' in relation to
ultra vires tax demands were so hopeless, and dependent upon a strained
reading of the speeches of Lord Goff which the House of Lords were not
bound by, that to seek to defend the result in the Court of Appeal based
upon the reasons they gave was a serious mistake. Unsurprisingly, the
Revenue went down 5-0 on this point.
Only Lord Hoffmann in the majority
in what he describes as a footnote, briefly alludes to the point that
the money was still payable, although the UK had behaved unlawfully
as a matter of Community law. He agrees with the Court of Appeal, rejecting
Park J's view, that there was no liability to pay, but gives no substantive
reasons [32]. The Scot in the court, Lord Hope, very disappointingly
agrees with Park J's interpretation of the legislation at [62], concluding
that there was liability to pay but that this didn't matter as there
was a causative mistake. The latter view cannot be right.
(2) Lord Walker seems to think that
neither the correct interpretation of section 32(1)(c) nor the question
of whether the claim was based upon mistake or absence of legal ground
arose for resolution. However if we accept, as he seems to do at [146]-[147]
that a mistake must be an essential element of the cause of action under
section 32(1)(c), it is hard to see how the second question does not
arise. In DMG the absence of legal ground, if there was one,
was not triggered by the mistake but by the contravention of European
Union law. If restitution follows where there is an absence of legal
ground, the mistake made was not an essential element of the cause of
action and section 32(1)(c) is not triggered.
Whilst Lord Walker's toying with Peter's
'Pyramid' at [158] is interesting, I wonder whether it is consistent
with the result he reaches. Only if the mistake, at the base of the
pyramid, triggers the absence of legal ground higher up is it an essential
part of the cause of action (eg a contract of sale where the price has
been paid but the subject matter does not exist.)
Lord Hoffmann sees the point, I think,
but I am puzzling over his answer, at [22]
That does not seem to me inconsistent
with the existence of the mistake not being essential to the cause
of action but merely one example of a case which falls within a more
general principle, just as one could have (say, for the purposes of
limitation) a category called "clinical negligence" without
implying that it is a cause of action different in nature from other
kinds of negligence. He is saying, I think, that mistake
need not be an essential part of the cause of action for the purposes
of section 32(1)(c), but I am not sure I follow his reasoning as to
why not. If anyone can help me out I'd be grateful.
(3) On whether there was a mistake
the differences between Lords Hoffmann and Hope are those which where
ascertainable from KB
v Lincoln. Hoffmann is quite explicit in deeming there to be
a mistake where the law has changed because of judicial decision ([23])
as he admits, this can be read as supporting the Birks view ([28]) that
it is better not to try and square this with the orthodox approach that
the transfer is vitiated by any mistake present in the claimant's mind,
but rather to accept that the true basis of recovery is absence of legal
ground. Lords Hope and Walker seem to me to place more emphasis on finding
a real mistake.
(4) Lord Brown's point will have to
be paid for by some litigant in the future.
(5) The shame is that a lot of time
and effort has been spent rebutting the argument from 'exclusivity'
which deservedly went down 5-0, when counsel's time, and their Lordships
lengthy speeches, would more profitably have been spent focusing on
other issues. <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |